Matter or Not Matter?
The first (negative) definition of consciousness is often
formulated as "consciousness is what distinguishes a human being from
the animal or inanimate body". This definition, however tautological
it may seem, conveys a clear idea of a specific feature in conscious
beings that makes them essentially different from the rest of the
world. Categories like "the spirit", or "an idea", were commonly used
as the opposites of "matter", or "the body", to express this
difference: consciousness was said to belong basically to the realm
of the ideal, rather than that of the material. But is this
distinction of material and immaterial sides of the world adequate
enough?
One historically known solution is provided by abstract
monism, denying the existence of one of the opposites: either
everything is called "matter", in a kind of vulgar (naive,
intuitive, mechanistic, metaphysical, or natural-scientific)
materialism, or inversely, everything is claimed to originate from
some side of consciousness, like in innumerable variety of idealistic
teachings. It should be noted that idealism is much more diverse than
vulgar materialism, which is associated with a higher level of
abstraction and more distant relation to practical activity. The
attempts to substantiate idealism with materialistic elements, and to
enrich primitive materialism through somehow accounting for the ideal,
may lead to different kinds of dualism, which does not relate
consciousness to the non-conscious world, but rather admits their
independent existence. Depending on the proportion and arrangement of
materialistic and idealistic elements, one could distinguish logical
dualism of the Cartesian type, agnosticism, positivism, pragmatism,
realism etc. This cannot overcome the inherent incompleteness of the
two types of abstract monism, since the opposites are combined in
an abstract way, rather than synthesized, and they merely coexist
as different ideas within the same thought, hindering any congruence
and consistency.
Abstract monism and dualism are not constructive, in the sense
that they try to merely expel the problem of relating consciousness to
the non-conscious, so that no further study is possible. In
abstraction, the opposites are either identified (everything is
conscious, or everything is non-conscious), or they are simply
superimposed as entirely independent and unrelated entities. As a
result, one cannot speak of formation, or development of
consciousness; the ideal is imagined to be eternal and unchangeable,
and all the observable diversity of the world is either attributed to
the chaotic nature of matter, of denied as an illusion, an
imagination, a dream.
The only solution that can bridge the abyss between the conscious
and the non-conscious is to admit that consciousness is yet another
manifestation of something present in the non-conscious things,
processes etc., different in quality, but not in kind. In other words,
consciousness does not emerge from nothing—rather, it forms as a
natural continuation of natural development, being yet another level
of hierarchy.
But is it possible to preserve the integrity of the world and
escape its splitting into two non-intersecting realms, while asserting
the qualitative difference of consciousness (or its counterparts in
the non-conscious nature) from the other sides of the world? Isn?t it
a kind of dualism too? Yes, if no development is admitted and all the
entities are thought to be existing for ever in the same form, or a
variety of forms. No, if any distinction is to refer to a specific
level of hierarchy, or stage of development, becoming a unity on a
higher level.
The principal problem of philosophy
The principle of the integrity of the world is the cornerstone of
philosophy as such, and no treatment can be called philosophical if it
does not try to build a unified picture of the world, and suggest a
unified approach to its creative assimilation. This integrative
principle unfolds in a triple view:
-
Uniqueness. Nothing can exist "outside" the world, and the
very thought of another world puts that "another world" within the
world, where the thought has been initiated. There is only one world,
which could be formulated as: the world is all.
-
Universality. The wold is diverse, and it comprises any
possible distinction, thus consisting of innumerable partial "sub-
worlds", so that every distinct part of the world plays the role of a
world for its constituents. The world is bound to shape itself in
every possible way, and go through all the possible manifestations. In
other words, the world is everything.
-
Unity. Any two things are somehow connected in the world,
however different they may seem. Specifically, any thing is virtually
equivalent to its environment which complements it to the world. That
is, the world is a whole.
This 3U principle may seem to be too general to offer any
practical implications. However, it may be unfolded and applied to any
specific situation, so that the philosophy of any kind of things could
be derived from the unity of the world. In particular, the integrity
of every separate part of the world acting as a world within itself is
to obey the triple principle, which gives clues to understanding how a
conscious being can create worlds. Yet another immediate consequence
of the unity of the world is that every two things in the world have
something in common, and phenomena akin to consciousness can be found
on any other level. That is, one is sure to encounter analogs of
conscious behavior in inanimate or biological systems, so that their
study would help to comprehend human consciousness, bringing in more
understanding of which portion of their existence can be called
conscious and which cannot.
The fundamental principle of the integrity of the world suggests a
constructive approach to study development of consciousness and
subjectivity, since it relates them to the rest of the world and
indicates where they fit in the whole, and how they grow out of its
syncretic uniformity.
1. The world as matter
At any level, the world is comprised of many coexisting things
that move and interact according to the natural laws appropriate for
that level. There is nothing else in the world, and every phenomenon
can only be instantiated in a number of things interacting with each
other in a definite way, which constitutes its material side.
Everything is material in this sense, since everything exists in the
same world, and there are no different worlds that would not be a part
of the only world embracing them all.
However, for every particular thing, being material does not mean
that there is nothing in it except matter. An idea like that is
incompatible with the very existence of different things, as if one
did not distinguish golden decorations from sheer bar of gold, or a
painting from a dirty rug. Such an exaggerated "materialism" can
dominate under certain social conditions: thus, a typical bourgeois
cannot think of a work of art, or a scientific discovery, otherwise
than in terms of money invested in it; similarly, a hungry person can
hardly appreciate fine cookery, until the pains of hunger get
discharged.
Vulgar materialism does not distinguish the properties of things
from the things themselves; in the bourgeois philosophical literature,
the very word "materialism" only refers to that very kind of
materialism, as if there were no other, more consistent materialistic
philosophies, such as dialectical materialism.
Speaking of consciousness, the materialistic approach would seek
for its material support, the bodily things and their interactions
that lead to the phenomena associated with subjectivity. That is, no
spirit can exist outside material things, and no explanation of
consciousness is possible unless its material substrate is indicated.
However, spirit can never be reduced to matter, and one has to find
out, in which respect it is different.
2. The world as reflection
The shapes and properties of material things, their arrangement
and involvement in other things, their motion and interaction, their
development—all those manifestations of things are
different from their matter, though they could not appear without
matter. Every thing is characterized by its place in the whole of the
world—or in a system of things involved in a common motion—and
this is the ideal aspect of the thing, as an opposite to
material.
Since the world is unique, it cannot communicate with anything
else, and any relation of material things is a special case of the
world's universal relation to itself, reflection. The world is
reflected in itself, and it "returns" to itself with every act of
interaction, and it reproduces itself in every process of development.
This reflexivity is as ubiquitous as materiality, and as important for
the integrity of the world.
The overestimation of reflection is a distinctive feature of
philosophical idealism, of either objective or subjective kind. For
primitive minds, it looks like magic, that the same material can take
so many different shapes, and the same shape can be cast in different
materials. Also, considering reflection in an abstract way as
absolutely opposite to matter will necessarily demand inventing
somebody, who would impose shapes on raw matter, producing things.
Primitive people observed their own ability to produce certain kinds
of things, and they fancied that any thing at all (including humans)
must be produced by some mysterious being, a god. This is the usual
way abstractions distort the picture of the world.
Consciousness should be related to the ideal aspect of the world,
thus being put in the same row as existence, motion, life. That is,
consciousness is not material on itself, but it can only exist as a
relation between material bodies. The specificity of this relation is
yet to be determined, but the very kinship to the other processes and
properties in the world is already a solid basis for constructive
study.
3. The world as substance
According to the principle of integrity of the world, its material
and ideal sides cannot exist without each other. The reality
of every thing is the unity of its materiality and ideality, and the
very distinction between the material and the ideal may only refer to
a definite way of unfolding the hierarchy of the whole.
Like vulgar materialism and idealism resulted from exaggerating,
respectively, the ideas of matter and reflection, the idea of
substance primary to both matter and reflection has historically been
made an abstract foundation of a number of philosophies (Spinoza,
modern pragmatism, philosophical relativism etc.). However, isolation
of the world's substantiality from the material and ideal levels is
bound to get lost in unsolvable problems, and it cannot remove the
ideological conflict between materialism and idealism. The only true
solution would be synthetic: the material and the ideal are the two
sides of the same reality, and they cannot exist without each other.
In particular, this means that any consistently objective study must
consider the ideal component of the object, and virtually its relation
to the subject; however, one does not need to introduce consciousness,
to describe the non-conscious world, since there are forms of
reflection more appropriate at that level.
Every real thing can become a material constituent of a higher-
level formation—but this would not remove its ideal aspect; the
distinction of the material and the ideal is hence relative,
depending on the level of consideration—which, however, does not
make them any less opposite. It could be observed that a thing
serving as matter for a higher-level thing is ideal in a different
respect than the thing made of it. There is hierarchy in both
matter and reflection, and any reality is hierarchical, the levels of
hierarchy reproducing the phases of development. Any hierarchy could
be understood as matter becoming reflection, and reflection becoming
matter, and it is this mutual penetration that constitutes reality.
To grasp the reality of consciousness, one has to understand how
its ideal nature is related to the material implementations. That is,
there are certain properties of matter that are indispensable for
consciousness formation, and the presence of consciousness is to leave
material traces in the world. One is to study the historical forms of
consciousness, as well as the possible directions of its future
development.
Levels of reflection
As indicated, the roots of consciousness are to be sought for in
the ideal side of things, and ideality is hierarchical. That is, we
need to find the level of hierarchy, at which consciousness enters the
world, and the same level is to be also marked by the appearance of
the subject. Presumably, this must be a fundamental distinction, to
reproduce the drastic difference of conscious and non-conscious
reflection. We know only one as fundamental distinction, that of
living creatures and inanimate things. Hence the hierarchy of
reflection could be expressed in the triadic scheme, ordering the
levels of ideality by their generality:
-
Existence. This is the most general form of ideality, which
can be ascribed to anything in the world, including inanimate things.
Something must first of all exist, to have any specific features.
There may be different kinds of existence, differing by their specific
forms of being, motion and development. These special existences may
be hierarchically organized, in their turn. However, they all are
characterized as the levels of existence. Following one of the
possible directions of development, from syncretism to analyticity,
one comes to the distinction of inanimate existence and life.
-
Life. This is a special kind of existence characterized by the
distinction and opposition of an organism and its environment, which
may include other organism. All the laws of non-organic motion and
development apply to living beings as well, but there also are new
regularities applicable only on this level. As existence, a thing is
syncretically reflecting the world, being a part of it; inversely, the
thing is syncretically reflected in the world, being virtually
identical to its environment. On the level of life one encounters
external reflection, when an individual organism is essentially
a part of the genus, and its relation to the world is mediated by the
creatures of the same, or a different kind. While similar indirect
relations may be found in inanimate nature as random and optional,
they constitute the basis of existence for a living organism, which
cannot live without quite definite interactions with other organisms
(metabolism).
-
Activity. This is the most universal kind of life, allowing
for subjectivity. The living thing and its environment get re-united
on this level due to the formation of an "artificial" environment,
culture; however, this unity differs from the syncretism of
existence, and the identity of the individual and its environment has
to be repeatedly broken and reproduced in a cyclic way. The subject is
originally a living creature, but a very special kind of living
creature that can be included in the society of other similar beings,
reproducing the ways of behavior developed in this society regardless
of their immediate physiological significance. This implies a new,
internal reflection, or communication, which serves to
transfer the modes of action from one member of the society to
another. While similar transfer of behavioral schemes appears in
animals only as a transitory feature, communication plays the dominant
role in the subject, so that every act is socially oriented, and
represented in every individual as such, which is called
consciousness.
The mind, reason, consciousness etc. arise on a certain stage of
development, forming a specific level of hierarchy, namely, the social
level. However, consciousness must be always associated with some
kind of life, and it is certainly related to inanimate existence.
Consciousness is not matter, but it cannot exist without a material
implementation, which does not need to be unique. The world is
hierarchical, and a higher-level formation can be implemented in
different combinations of lower-level elements, which constitute its
material base, while the way of implementation represents its ideal
side. This is the germ of consciousness in the inanimate world.
Hence, there is no unbridgeable abyss between conscious and non-conscious
existence, and one could find a continuum of intermediate
levels both between the "physical" existence and life, as well as
between conscious and non-conscious life. Still, the level of
consciousness is qualitatively different from life and inanimate
existence, and it can be represented in any particular biological
system only to a certain degree, so that both the form of
implementation would restrict the possible manifestations of
consciousness, and the participation in conscious acts would influence
biological development, leading to the forms that could never be
stable without social support.
|